I: Competing discourses
According to the political theorist, John Gray, ‘the mounting panic’ induced by the rise of China has sparked a ‘fundamentalist revival’ of the European Enlightenment, which he says has ‘become a sort of magic amulet’ to clutch to the heart ‘as a talisman against fear.’1 The journalists Will Hutton and John Pomfret, the political scientist Minxin Pei and the International Relations scholar, John Lee, are among the many advocates of this movement – all believe that
John Gray dismisses such arguments as ‘curiously anglocentric’, claiming instead that the largest economic expansion in history has managed to occur without any of the institutions that such advocates insist are universally necessary, such as the rule of law and property rights, having ever been in place. ‘In fact,’ says Gray, ‘as
Both of these views, I will argue, are problematic. The pessimists of Enlightenment, with their various gloom prophesies, are blind to the fact that the Chinese, over the past twenty-five years, have in fact been steadily developing the institutions of Enlightenment, with their progress to date already ‘radical and deep’, as the American sociologist Doug Guthrie has so thoroughly documented in his study on China and Globalization.4 Their belittling of China’s achievements in the areas of human rights, the rule of law and democratic reforms can be read, as John Gray concludes, as revelations of their own unconscious wish for China to fail – as manifestations, if you like, of an arrogant ethnocentrism.5
While I agree with Gray’s assessment of these Enlightenment fundamentalists, he too seems not to appreciate the role that
II: Gray’s pluralism verses the discourse of Enlightenment
Like John Gray, I believe that the over-critical attitude that many foreigners have towards
While I strongly admire Enlightenment values (most people do) I recognise also that the tradition has led to a number of serious failings, all of which, as Theodor Adorno argued, stem from its undialectical vision.
The Enlightenment, despite its noble values, has repeatedly led its faithful down the road to making dangerous, universalising abstractions, its rigid, instrumental Reason often suppressing differences that lead to systematic violence.
In their Dialectics of Enlightenment, Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer argued that where scientific rationality was initially used to attack religious, superstitious and mythical dogma in the name of free inquiry, tolerance and an open society, soon enough scientific rationality was unleashed against those ethical values that had inspired its use in the first place. ‘Knowledge’ became divorced from ‘information’, norms from facts, and the scientific method increasingly freed from any commitment to liberation, transformed nature into an object of domination. Reason, once the great liberating force, became ‘instrumental’.7
When viewed this way, the Enlightenment can be seen as the progenitor of a society in which the manipulation of others by an all powerful state represents the
Whereas many see the Enlightenment as the movement towards freedom and democracy, I agree with Adorno, who saw it as leading to the development of modern states, which in turn develop systems of control and bureaucratic administration that extend greater and greater control over the individual.
Adorno, unlike most of today’s postmodern thinkers, was a Marxian who sought to rehabilitate projects of coherency. He argued precisely the opposite to what postmodern deconstructionists advocate. In his view, deconstruction can only do just that – deconstruct the system. It cannot genuinely get outside the system. For that, argued Adorno, we need to add an extra distinct dimension to our knowledge. It is not that we need to dismantle systems, but that we need to interweave them with an alternative. We have to not deconstruct, but to reconstruct our knowledge. This is exactly what I have been trying to achieve in regards to my own understanding of today’s
We live in a world of paradox, and so Enlightenment needs to recognise such paradox in order to be truly enlightened. Reason, to be reasonable, must counterbalance itself with its opposite. This is a universal phenomenon – there is never any unity without internal opposition.
Without such internal opposition, Reason itself simply becomes a question of power: the object of Enlightenment knowledge simply subjects the Other to itself. When, for example, English farmers occupied Native American lands upon arrival at
As Yvonne Sherratt points out in her book, Adorno’s Positive Dialectic, ‘Enlightenment to be enlightened, needs Subjects who can communicate rationally, and to do so, they need not attempt to transcend their own humanity, but rather, they need to be so intensely receptive to their world that they can be, in one moment fully rational and in the other, fully absorbed.’9 Failure to do so in my view can only result in the formation of views that are fundamentally ethnocentric, and that are hence potentially dangerous.
Indeed, it has been the Enlightenment’s undialectical, half-baked concept of Reason that has led not only to the ethnocentrism of Europeans, but also, consequently, to so much of the world’s suffering. Even today, Western countries continue to glory in spreading ‘enlightened’ religion and democracy to the ‘backward native cultures’, and their colonial adventures they justify by their ‘enlightened’ superiority – an alibi for the conquest of developing countries. ‘In its own eyes, Western humanism is the love of humanity,’ wrote the French existentialist philosopher, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, ‘but to others it is merely the custom and institution of a group of men, their password, and sometimes their battle cry.’10
Enlightenment thinkers may very well have promised a steady progressive improvement in manner, morals, technology and general social well-being, but the harsh reality is that the world today continues to suffer from unprecedented levels of state sponsored violence and economic exploitation. Consider for example, what is happening in Afghanistan and Iraq right now – imperialist adventures, justified using Enlightenment values: ‘we must save the good people of Iraq from the tyranny of dictatorship, and help them to install a wonderful democracy modelled on our own,’ goes the argument. The history of the 19th and 20th centuries is the history of such violent conquests and hypocrisy, and the 21st century doesn’t look like shaping up to be any better.
Enlightenment then, rather than being the great demistifying and emancipating force promised, has instead turned out to be its very opposite, because it argues that we can cover or encompass the world through our reason and our language.
Only by adopting a more dialectical approach to Reason, can we Westerners gain a deeper, fairer, more balanced set of attitudes towards the Chinese Other. We need to more fully absorb ourselves into the Chinese mind, into the Chinese way of seeing and doing things, if we want to be able to make more rational, more reasoned, more enlightened judgements about China, its people, and its institutions.
The pluralist approach endorsed by John Gray provides such a way forward. In his book, Enlightenment’s Wake, Gray argues that ‘if there are ways of life embodying genuine forms of human flourishing that require as their matrices non-liberal social and political structures, then a pluralist moral theory which recognises such forms of human flourishing must be complemented by a pluralist political theory, which recognises forms of political order that are not, and will never become, liberal.’13
‘The pluralist standard of assessment of any regime,’ he suggests, ‘is whether it enables its subjects to coexist in a Hobbesian peace while renewing their distinctive forms of common life.’14 When assessing regimes using this standard, adds Gray, our criticisms should not invoke universalist conceptions of human rights or democracy, since ‘there is no democratic project that has authority over all peoples and all circumstances.’15
The political scientist Daniel A. Bell, also believes that ‘there are morally legitimate alternatives to Western-style liberal democracy in the East-Asia region,’ and that what is right for East Asians ‘does not simply involve implementing Western-style political practices when the opportunities present itself; it involves drawing upon East-Asian political realities and cultural traditions that are defensible to contemporary East-Asians.’16
Many people will, I know, object to the pluralist approach, seeing it as an endorsement of moral relativism. There are no such things as ‘Asian values’ they will say, for Asians value freedom just as much as do Americans and Australians and everyone else. Asians too want to elect their own governments, they too want access to as much information as possible and to have the opportunities to express themselves as they please. Human rights, so say the opponents of relativism, are universal.
I agree that all people value individual rights and that everyone holds dear to their hearts the idea that each individual’s physical and mental integrity ought be respected, yet the empirical reality is that communal rights and individual rights very often do conflict. Since community cohesion and individual rights are both real goods, any morality, as Neil Levy suggests, must find a place for both: ‘a morality that does not find a place for individual rights at all is mistaken; but at the same time so is a morality that always allows such rights to trump social goods.’17
Eastern and Western conceptions of morality for example, while overlapping on a great many things, differ systematically in the emphasis each places on the value of individuality and community. These are real values, as David Wong, Daniel Bell and John Gray have all argued, but they are values that frequently clash. As Neil Levy explains:
In the West, we have resolved the tension between them largely, though not exclusively, in favour of individual rights. Thus we believe that each person has the right to express (almost) any opinion, no matter how false, stupid or vindictive. We allow people to exercise their right of free speech at the risk of endangering community solidarity, even promoting violence. To be sure, there are limits on this right. Several countries have laws banning public discourse calculated to incite racial hatred, for instance. Nevertheless, in general we believe that the threat to community solidarity, the risk of real violence, must be high before we are willing to countenance restrictions upon free speech....However, at least some Asian countries have taken almost exactly the opposite view: holding that language that represents any risk to community cohesion ought to be restricted unless there are very strong reasons to allow it.18
Some may try to deny that Asians value community solidarity more highly than do Westerners, arguing instead that the leaders of Asian countries exaggerate their population’s commitment to communal values for their own political ends. But there is a good deal of empirical evidence to show that East Asians do in fact value community solidarity more highly than do Westerners, ranging from the findings of psychologists in controlled experiments to the more impressionistic accounts of journalists, and as Neil Levy as pointed out, ‘it is not just the elites, those with the most to gain from the continuation of the current regimes, who report satisfaction with the choices these nations have made to emphasise the social over the individual. It is, apparently, the majority of ordinary people who think that their system is preferable to what they see as the over-emphasis on individuality in the West.’19 Indeed, even many Asian human rights activists express such ideas.
Not all societies give the same weight to the protection of individual rights over communal rights as does
Value-pluralism then, provides us with a powerful and plausible position from which to assess the Other, for as Neil Levy concludes, ‘it vindicates the tolerance of, and respect for, at least some cultures with moralities that differ from our own, by showing that the values they pursue are real values,’ and it ‘counsels humility for us in the face of difference, since if it is true we are forced to acknowledge that our morality is just one reasonable system among others. It therefore opens our eyes to difference, and liberates us from the constraints of excessive ethnocentrism.’23
At the same time, however, the pluralist standard of assessment allows one to avoid at least some of what relativism’s opponents see as its worst excesses, for ‘it does not advocate respect for all moralities, no matter what, but places constraints on what counts as a moral system worthy of such respect.’24 A society that places so much emphasis on one or another good that it allows no place at all for another important value, for example, may be deemed unworthy of our recognition.
In the essays that follow, empirically-verifiable research of both a qualitative and quantitative nature is used to explore
Other issues, like those of the Tibet Question, the Tiananmen Massacre,
NOTES
1 John Gray, ‘On top of the world?’ The Guardian,
2 Will Hutton, The Writing on the Wall: China and the West in the 21st Century, Little, Brown,
3 John Gray, ‘On top of the world?’
4 Doug Guthrie,
5 John Gray, ‘On top of the world?’ In the end, says Gray, ‘what Hutton and others like him fear most is not that the Chinese experiment will fail. It is that
6 Jacques deLisle, ‘Legalization without Democratization’ in Cheng Li (editor), China's Changing Political Landscape: Prospects for Democracy, Brookings Institution Press,
7 Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectics of Enlightenment, 1947, translated by J. Cumming, Verso, London, 1979, p.85
8 Ibid., pp.94-136 and pp.137-172.
9 Yvonne Sherratt, Adorno’s Positive Dialectic, Cambridge University Press,
10 Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Humanism and Terror: The Communist Problem, 1947, translated by John O'Neil, Transaction Publishers, 2000, p.776.
11 John Gray, Black Mass: Apocalyptic Religion and the Death of Utopia, Penguin,
12 Ibid., pp.70-71.
13 John Gray, Enlightenment’s Wake, Routledge,
14 Ibid., p.210
15 Ibid., p.210.
16 Daniel A. Bell, Beyond Liberal Democracy: political thinking for an East Asian context, Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 2006, p.8.
17 Neil Levy, Moral Relativism: A Short Introduction, Oneworld Publications,
18 Ibid., pp.197-198.
19 Ibid., pp.199-200.
20 Quoted from Time magazine,
21 Neil Levy, Moral Relativism, p.199.
22 David B. Wong, ‘Pluralistic Relativism’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Moral Concepts, Volume 20, pp.378-399.
23 Neil Levy, Moral Relativism, p.201.
24 Ibid., p.201.
25 Lin Yutang, My Country and My People, 1935, Foreign Language Teaching and Research
COMMENTS